Positivity, strict and otherwise

[recursive-types] [totality] [impredicativity]

In a total language, type definitions that refer to themselves must be restricted:

-- rejected by Coq
Inductive bad := r (c : bad -> nat).
-- rejected by Agda
data Bad : Set where
  r : (Bad → ℕ) → Curry

Here, the type bad is defined recursively as consisting of a function that accepts bad as an input. Allowing these negative definitions leads to Curry's paradox, and breaks totality.

The situation is more complicated if the recursive reference is underneath two function arrows:

-- also rejected by Coq
Inductive bad2 := r (c : (bad2 -> nat) -> nat).
-- also rejected by Agda
data Bad2 : Set where
  r : ((Bad2 → ℕ) → ℕ) → Bad2

This is not negative recursion: bad2 is not defined in terms of functions that accept bad2 values as an input, but in terms of functions that may provide bad2 values to their argument. This is said to be positive recursion (since all recursive references to bad2 occur to the left of an even number of function arrows), but not strictly positive (wherein all recursive references occur to the left of zero function arrows).

Recursive definitions which are positive yet not strictly positive can cause issues, as pointed out by Coquand and Paulin1. Their counterexample was translated into modern Coq by Sjöberg2, and reproduced here:

(* Counterexample by Thierry Coquand and Christine Paulin
   Translated into Coq by Vilhelm Sjöberg *)

(* Phi is a positive, but not strictly positive, operator. *)
Definition Phi (a : Type) := (a -> Prop) -> Prop.

(* If we were allowed to form the inductive type
     Inductive A: Type :=
       introA : Phi A -> A.
   then among other things, we would get the following. *)
Axiom A : Type.
Axiom introA : Phi A -> A.
Axiom matchA : A -> Phi A.
Axiom beta : forall x, matchA (introA x) = x.

(* In particular, introA is an injection. *)
Lemma introA_injective : forall p p', introA p = introA p' -> p = p'.
Proof.
  intros.
  assert (matchA (introA p) = (matchA (introA p'))) as H1 by congruence.
  now repeat rewrite beta in H1.
Qed.

(* However, ... *) 

(* Proposition: For any type A, there cannot be an injection
   from Phi(A) to A. *)

(* For any type X, there is an injection from X to (X->Prop),
   which is λx.(λy.x=y) . *)
Definition i {X:Type} : X -> (X -> Prop) := 
  fun x y => x=y.

Lemma i_injective : forall X (x x' :X), i x = i x' -> x = x'.
Proof.
  intros.
  assert (i x x = i x' x) as H1 by congruence.
  compute in H1.
  symmetry.
  rewrite <- H1.
  reflexivity.
Qed.  

(* Hence, by composition, we get an injection f from A->Prop to A. *)
Definition f : (A->Prop) -> A 
  := fun p => introA (i p).

Lemma f_injective : forall p p', f p = f p' -> p = p'.
Proof.
  unfold f. intros.
  apply introA_injective in H. apply i_injective in H. assumption.
Qed.

(* We are now back to the usual Cantor-Russel paradox. *)
(* We can define *)
Definition P0 : A -> Prop
  := fun x => 
       exists (P:A->Prop), f P = x /\ ~ P x.
  (* i.e., P0 x := x codes a set P such that x∉P. *)

Definition x0 := f P0.

(* We have (P0 x0) iff ~(P0 x0) *)
Lemma bad : (P0 x0) <-> ~(P0 x0).
Proof.
split.
  * intros [P [H1 H2]] H.
    change x0 with (f P0) in H1.
    apply f_injective in H1. rewrite H1 in H2.
    auto.
  * intros.
    exists P0. auto.
Qed.

(* Hence a contradiction. *)
Theorem worse : False.
  pose bad. tauto.
Qed.

This counterexample uses three ingredients: non-strictly-positive definitions, impredicativity (the ability for definitions of terms in Prop to quantify over all of Prop) and a universe type (the ability to refer to Prop itself as a type). It appears that all three are necessary:

  • The Calculus of Inductive Constructions, upon which Coq is based, is total, and has an impredicative Prop and a universe type for Prop, but requires all inductive definitions to be strictly positive.

  • System F is impredicative, and can encode (or be extended with) non-strictly-positive inductive types while remaining total (see Berger et al.3 for an example), but lacks a universe type.

  • The combination of non-strictly-positive inductive types and universe types is an unusual one, but poses no theoretical problems in the absence of impredicativity. See for instance the constructions of Abel4 or Blanqui5.

1

Section 3.1 of "Inductively defined types", Thierry Coquand and Christine Paulin, 1988.

3

Martin Hofmann’s Case for Non-Strictly Positive Data Types, Ulrich Berger, Ralph Matthes and Anton Setzer (2018)

4

Section 7.1 of A Semantic Analysis of Structural Recursion, Andreas Abel (1999)